Must we understand his refusal to accept some sort of cultural relativism as a disguise for an even stronger,
but more emotional motivated refusal: in the words of Foucault "that man would be erased" not as an effect of a
planned subjecticide, but as an inevitable result of an unintended subjectisuicide, exactly because western man
thought himself to be sui generis and universal? To formulate this in terms of this congress: does his quest
for man differ from that of for instance a philosopher like Husserl and a rationalistic, cartesian orientated
linguist like Noam Chomsky, to whom he is refering with approval. Or is he in spite of his own intentions and
precisely as a result of his comparisons with non western cultures advocating the disappearence of modern man
as Foucault and Barthes are explicitely doing? The second issue concerns his intercultural comparisons and the
expected mutual understanding. Yesterday we discussed Strasser's theses on human experience. The fourth thesis
stated that we can only understand an experience by referring to a similar experience we have had in the past.
In the discussion with Gyekye the Akan language and the specific connotations were explained and I asked myself
how I could understand the experiences from this culture? I agree: in our present world massmedia and all kind
of intercultural exchanges as Holenstein points out himself have created enough space for mutual understanding,
that is for a minimal level of communication that suffices for the limited purposes of international scientific
communication, trade, tourism and warfare. But is it possible to understand the specific experiences of an
'other individuality' within a foreign culture in another way then by renunciating our own schemes and trying
to live theirs for quite a while, in which case our 'individuality' must change fundamentally? To illustrate my
doubts I will concentrate upon Holenstein's thesis that in Japanese culture a similar form of autonomy as ours
can be traced.
1) Let me start with Holenstein's remarks on Foucault. To a certain extent he is right by remarking, "nicht
die Universalisten, die Relativisten (mit ihren Reden von 'der abendländische Kultur', 'der chinesischen
Philosophie') sind im Widerspruch zu ihrem eigenen Ansatz die schrecklichen Vereinfacher. So heißt es bei
Michel Foucault, wissenschaftgeschichtlich mit schlichten Fakten widerlegbar: "Dans une culture et à un
moment donné, il n'y a jamais qu'un episteme, qui définit les conditions de possibilité de
tout savoir'". A quotation from Les mots et les choses (The order of things) from 1966. I must admit, Foucault
is rather apodictic in his formulations and in spite of his own philosophical intentions he does not leave much
room for a second opinion. He gives his reader the impression that there is no way out. But in his forwords,
epilogues, programmatic interviews and methodological comments Foucault always reminds us of the very specific
configuration of cultural facts or the 'locality' his analysis is focused on. In this particular case he is
analysing the way scholars in western culture during a period of threehunderd years have been thinking, but
more important writing about man as a living, labouring and talking being. He points out that the question
"What is man?", anyway the way we understand it, could only be raised and answered after Kant. And that the
answer in terms of subjectivity, rationality and autonomy has been severely criticized, once we tried to
theorize traumatic historical events we underwent. As a result of that selfcritique Foucault finds it justified
to state, that "it is no longer possible to think in our day other than in the void left by man's
disappearance". There is no need to go into detail here. The main point is that if we want to speak of
Foucault's 'universalism' we must be aware of the fact that he, by analysing all kinds of material discourses,
retrospectively contructs the conditions of possibility from which these discourses have emerged. In other
words, in his pseudo transcendental discourse universal traits are the result of a specific methodological, so
called archeological 'gaze'. Moreover, there is always a specific, limited configuration of material
discourses. And, last but not least, as a true nietzschean thinker Foucault is aware of the fact that in every
knowledge a strategic intention, a will to truth, is hiding. This goes for the discourses he analyses, but also
for his own discourse. Just because of this aporetic trait Foucault cannot claim universalism. His book The
order of things is written in 1966. It still is influenced by a structuralist method, that is only denounced in
the forword of the second edition. That same time a discussion takes place with Chomsky. This discussion is
revealing because it pinpoints Chomsky as a cartesian rationalist, looking for universals by analysing language
from a structural point of view, much the same as Holenstein is proposing. Foucault outlines his project from a
contrary intention: he wants to draw our attention to the specific characteristics of a cultural period. Not to
the simularities, but to the irreducable differences that are repressed in order to produce these simularities.
He is proceeding this way to construe his argument that so called modern rationality is a discursively produced
and therefore limited concept, that even in Western culture can be contrasted to other historical rational
systems. This critique has its counterpart in a project to indicate and explore a new space within which 'new
forms of subjectivity' or selfexperiences can be articulated, finally appears to be Foucault's strategic
methodological intention. Holenstein is right: in The order of things Foucault still under the spell of
structuralism's need for transhistorical explanations admits, that for our culture as a Greek Christian
tradition there are "fundamental codes those gouverning language, its schemes of perception, its exchanges, its
techniques, its values, the hierarchy of its practices established for every man...". But he immediately adds
that these fundamental codes are necessarely transformed in different periods in such a way that, if ever, they
can only be experienced through a grid, an episteme. The practises of signification, as a result of which the
experiences of people living in that specific period are formed, are different in each period. As we can see to
a certain extent Foucault like Holenstein accepts invariants as the fundamental code within a culture, but he
realises that this code is a retrospective construction from primarily given differences. From a strategic
point of view, i.e. in order to dismantle the universal pretentions of modernity, which is caught in its own
paradoxes, he does not get tired of stressing the constituents of invariants: differences. In this sense only,
Holenstein is right in saying that "manche Relativisten bestreiten, daß es, von Trivialitäten
abgesehen, interkulturelle Invarianten gibt." This point is stressed in the latter works of Foucault,
especially part 2 and 3 of the history of sexuality, L'usage des plaisirs and Le souci de soi. In these texts
Foucault analyses Greek texts that describe and prescribe the behavior of Greek males in order to control their
physical energies, their homes and their desire towards young males. The result of this disciplining is not
subjectivity, but another form of selfexperience. In spite of the triumphant reactions of his critics, the
'final' Foucault finally does not reconstruct the roots of western subjectivity i.e. uncovers invariants , but
he shows that even within our own culture the roots are not to be identified as the origin, but as a dispersion
of irreduceable differences. In short, even Foucault acknowledges a certain tension between cultural variants
and invariants, but he is aware of the fact that a 'will to truth' retrospectively invents and constructs and
not reconstructs or discovers the invariants. To me Holenstein's will to truth is stated by himself at the end
of his article on Husserl: "Totalitätsansprüche, das lehrt Husserls Schicksal, drohen weniger global
als vielmehr national und regional, innerhalb einzelner Staaten, Gesellschaften, sozialer Schichten. Schutz
bieten können, das lehren ähnliche Schicksale heute, weltweite Kommunikations und
Solidarisierungsmöglichkeiten. In dieser Hinsicht sind Universalismus und Pluralismus miteinander nicht
nur verträglich, sie sind einander auch förderlich."
2) I think Holenstein's critique on Barthes can be commented in more or less the same way. Barthes'
description of his individual experience of a few weeks in Tokyo and if you have had that experience on your
own for a longer period you certainly know it is devastating is made from a radical semiotic point of view. In
the preface of L'empire des signes from 1970 Barthes stresses his methodological refusal to master the language
in order to be confronted first with the exotic and impenetrable character of Japanese culture, but also with
the inadequacy of the arbitrary western codes we are formed by: "I can also, without claiming the least
representability or analytical truthvalue (as the everlasting presumption of Western discourse) single out of
that world (over there) a few characteristics and form them (in a graphical or linguïstic sense) into a
arbitrary system. I will call that system 'Japan'." Of course this total discursive isolation has had its
effect on the interpretation of the gestures and the behavior of the Japanese he has met. Hide Ishiguro
criticizes Barthes justly for the radical opposition he makes between Japanese and western culture. She accuses
him of an the implicit presupposition that to him Westerners are "autonomous Cartesians, each convinced of
having privileged acces to his inner self". I do not think this is correct, given Barthes' other writings, in
which he criticizes this illusion. But her critique is of course endorsed by Holenstein, who after all wants to
draw our attention to the simularities. But neither Hide Ishiguro nor Holenstein acknowledge Barthes' semiotic
intention. More radically than Foucault Barthes wants to point out the irreduceable differences we are
confronted with, once we eliminate the delusive appearance of social and linguïstic codes. Not because we
eliminate them. Of course, one could argue with Holenstein that, unless one learns a basic form of language and
at least familiarizes with social costumes, the simularities never will be grasped. But we should ask ourselves
whether that communicative minimum only gives us the impression that we understand the behavior and intentions
of the others? The claim Holenstein holds, i.e. that differences between cultures can be reduced to differences
in hierarchy, seems to me the result of an opposite attitude as Barthes'. I don't grasp the meaning of his
attempt to focus our attention to the intracultural differences at the end of the second text. What is it he
wants us to see? Is he trying to proclaim his conviction that eventually, in spite of all the differences,
Japanese and Westerners are structurally the same, because they both are raising children or making decisions
for themselves? If so, does that say anything of their individual experiences and the specific quality of their
individuality? I don't think so, but some of Holenstein's remarks do indicate in this direction: "Als
ausgesprochen und ausgeprägt westlich wird immer wieder das Bestehen auf der Autonomie des Individuums
angeführt. (...) Sie mag sich in weniger gewohnten Weisen manifestieren, wie in Japan z.B. der Kult der
individuellen Stärke und Selbstbeherrschung in Samurai Filmen und Zenschriften nahelegt". I don't find
this example very convincing and I would like to invite Kojima sensei to comment on this aspect later on.
Samuraifilms, especially the popular chambara, are one thing, Zenwritings another, but I don't think that
autonomy is an adequate category either to identify the attemps of samurai to control their behavior or to
understand the disciplined way they commit seppuku or harakiri in order to save the honour of both their
superiors and their families, dead or alive. And therefore save their selfrespect. This selfrespect to my
opinion has nothing to do with our autonomy. Our autonomy implicates a last ressort to fall on apart from
our social setting. A rationality we call duty. Only by universalizing and therefore including every 'animal
rationabile' it can mask the exclusion of the other, while the selfrespect of the Japanese seems to be
everything but the exclusion of the other. Their 'self'respect is more likely to be a function of the
obligations one has towards the others. Guided by a strict hierarchy the debts (on) towards the living and the
dead have to be repaid in a adequate proportion (giri) in order to preserve the harmony (wa) of the group.
Holenstein is so eager to prove his point on the comparison of two sorts of autonomy, that he even takes the
critique of a 19th century Japanese painter, Kuwayama Gyokusho, on the realistic aspect of Chinese painting in
those days as an expression of the autonomy of art, so praised in Western society from the middle of the 19th
century. He thereby ignores on the one hand the zenboeddhist round of Japanese critique, on the other the
specifity of avantgarde art and the social setting in which this could develop itself in our culture.
Avantgarde as a continuing revolt against every heteronomous determination of the selfconsciousness as the
extreme expression of Western autonomy. A revolt that could never have been institutionalised in Japan as
Holenstein affirms when he speaks of the peasantrevolts: "Man protestierte nicht gegen die bestehende Ordnung,
sondern allein gegen ihren Mißbrauch mit maßlosen steuerlichen Belastungen". He does not tell that
the only way for the peasant spokesmen to complaint is by committing seppuku or harakiri, once he had broken
his loyalty to his lord. To end my remarks on Holenstein's comparison of Japanese and Western autonomy I focus
your attention to his view on the unique relation between the Japanese mother and her child (amae). The total
emotional dependence of the child upon his mother and her absolute devotion towards him is according to him a
"Antrieb zur individuellen Autonomie". He refers to the psychiatrist Doi Takeo to prove his argument, but it is
the same Doi who points out that this total dependence correlates with a need of protection that is persued in
the rest of the adult lives. It institutionalizes not only the on, but destroys every urge to take the
initiative. The Japanese even have a verb for this pretending dependence: amaeru. To me this seems the opposite
of our Western autonomy. There is a qualitive difference between this autonomy and the Japanese 'selfrespect'.
To my opinion this is but one of the examples that undermines Holensteins thesis, that "was Kulturen
unterscheidet, ist weniger eine spezifische Eigenschaft oder ein spezifisches Bündel von Eigenschaften
(...) als der unterschiedliche Stellenwert, der in ihnen einzelnen Eigenschaften zukommt".
Nevertheless Holenstein's theses are very tempting. He acknowledges the differences within cultures and
questions the absoluteness of demarcations between cultures. With his claim that intracultural variations seem
to be as extensive as intercultural, he is in a way subscribing the positions of thinkers of difference like
Foucault, although he attacks their indeed, sometimes very obscure strategies. But nevertheless he is not
prepared to draw the seemingly inevitable conclusion of a mitigated relativism. Of course, even Foucault must
admit that there is communication between cultures, subcultures or epoches. He is, however, not prepared to
admit that we, so called autonomous subjects, can manipulate this process of exchange by appealing to something
in ourselves or our culture that corresponds with the Other. The exchanges happen by virtue of
(language)practises, in which we have to be confronted with the other and our selves. He probably would have
accused Holenstein of universalizing one of those strategies by indicating at the structural linguïstic
similarities. Can Holenstein's dialectical approach be understood as one of the disguised attempts to rescue
western subjectivity or as Foucault calls him: Man from disappearing?
|